Scientists sometimes conceal a lack of knowledge with vague words216477e27a4d28860d52a1312099ac78

You can’t
kill a virus, common wisdom contends, because viruses aren’t alive to begin
with.

Yet some viruses
sure act like they’re alive. And in fact, you can find biologists and
philosophers who will insist that viruses do deserve a branch on the tree of
life. Still, many oth­er experts refuse to confer viruses with life status.

Debates
about viruses as life-forms (or not) have raged for decades. But as more and
more data on viral vitality accumulate, the disagreements do not diminish. Perhaps
that’s because the argument is not really about the nature of viruses. Rather
it’s about the definition of life. Scientists can’t agree on that,
either.

Science’s
inability to define life reveals not merely a lack of lexicographic
dexterity, but also signifies a broader issue — the peculiar way that science’s
relationship with reality is connected to science’s relationship with words.

Words are
obviously indispensable for scientists, both to communicate among themselves
and to report their findings to the rest of civilization. Even in the most
mathematical of sciences, words must be attached to symbols in order to relate
mathematical relationships to real-world phenomena. Words like energy or
force or stress tensor describe a physical entity corresponding
to a symbol in an equation.

But many
scientific ideas do not reduce to a neat mathematical expression, so the words
are on their own. And sometimes the ideas originate with the words. Throughout
history, scientists have often coined a word before fully formulating the underlying
idea. As Johann Wolfgang von Goethe wrote in his poetic play Faust, in
the absence of ideas, words can come to the rescue. “With words, the mind does
its conceiving,” reads one translation. (Or, in another version, “If your
meaning’s threatened with stagnation, then words come in, to save the
situation.”)

So sometimes
scientists adopt a term, and use it widely, even though no precise definition
of that term is universally accepted. Life is an obvious example. It’s a
word that most people instinctively understand yet nobody can define to everybody
else’s satisfaction.

“We all think we can recognize a living organism when we see one,” biochemists Athel Cornish-Bowden and María Luz Cárdenas wrote in the February issue of the journal BioSystems, “but it is not so easy to give a definition of ‘living’ that includes all the entities we consider to be alive, and excludes the ones we do not.”

Some
proposed definitions of life, for instance, include the capacity to reproduce,
note Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas, of Aix-Marseille University in France. Sounds
good, but what about mules? They can’t reproduce, but most people would agree
that mules are alive, the biochemists point out. “Taking the minority view that
mules cannot be regarded as alive does not solve the problem, because many
people, including many distinguished biologists, have passed the age when they
can reproduce, but would dispute any claim that they are not alive.”

Life is one of many common scientific
words that elude precise definition. And scientists have often used much vaguer
terms, typically as stand-ins for primitive, imprecise ideas — some that turned
out to be in essence correct, others totally wrong.

Ancient
Greeks, for instance, invented the word atom to describe the tiniest,
“uncuttable” pieces of matter. But no Greek had any real knowledge of what an
atom actually was like (and of course, they had no proof that atoms even
existed, as atom denier Aristotle vigorously argued). But the concept turned
out to be roughly right. Chemists in the 18th century, on the other hand,
insisted that fire depended on a substance called phlogiston. But phlogiston
was just a word, linked to an idea that turned out to be completely erroneous.
Similarly impetus, a term popular in medieval times for discussing
Aristotle’s views on how objects in motion kept moving, lost its momentum once
Galileo and Newton debunked Aristotle.

In more
modern times, the word gene, like atom, initially described a
primitive idea, not yet fully formed. (Gene, referring to an element of
heredity, was coined by the Danish botanist Wilhelm Johannsen in 1909, decades
before anybody knew how DNA worked.) Over the last century the definition of
gene has evolved, though it’s still not as rigorously defined as all scientists would like.

Part of science’s
problem in linking words to meanings is (as experts in language repeatedly
remind us) that there’s always a gap between a word and the reality it
represents. “The word is not the thing,” the semanticist S.I. Hayakawa emphasized
in his famous book Language in Thought and Action, just as a map is not
identical to the territory it depicts. Some scientific terms serve as pretty
reliable maps of reality, while others turn out to be decoys leading to dead
ends. A major part of scientific progress is narrowing the gap between word and
thing — transforming vague labels into more specific symbols.

It’s easy
to find many current examples of scientific terms that mimic knowledge while
actually disguising a lack of understanding. “Dark matter” and “dark energy”
must exist, physicists insist, while admitting nobody yet can say what they
actually are. Other deep mysteries baffling today’s best scientific detectives
also reflect an inability to bring words closer to things. Consciousness
is a prime example, referring to mental processes that have eluded anything
approaching a coherent physical description. Intelligence comes a little
closer to intelligible meaning, but not sufficiently to avoid all sorts of
arguments about reproducing it artificially.

Another
favorite problem word for physicists, time, poses a plethora of puzzles.
For one thing, it has multiple meanings — time of day is not the same
thing as period of time is not the same thing as time travel. Physicists
still squabble over why time’s arrow points only to the future and whether the flow of time is an
objective physical fact or an illusion in a “block universe” where all events are already
sitting there, just waiting for a conscious observer to witness them. Of
course, it may turn out that time’s mysteries are problems more of language
than of physics. “We run into puzzles about the concept of time and then
we say, oh, what a terrible thing,” the physicist John Archibald
Wheeler once said. “We don’t realize we’re the source of the
puzzle because we invented the word.”

Only time
(another meaning) will tell whether words like time and consciousness
express ideas of greater depth than scientific understanding has yet reached. Maybe
consciousness and time will turn out to be prophetic terms, like atom,
that foreshadow the emergence of reliable scientific concepts. Or maybe time
and consciousness (and who know what other words) will go poof! like phlogiston.

In any
case, it’s remarkable how often words masquerading as ideas can eventually lead
to successful scientific endeavors. Entire fields of scientific research have grown
from word-seeds invented in the absence of substantiated ideas — atom
and gene being the best examples. As Goethe went on to note in Faust:

“With
words fine arguments can be weighted, with words whole systems can be created.”

But it
might be a good idea to remember that the character speaking those lines was
Mephistopheles, Goethe’s representative of the devil himself.

Read More